|
Adorno at the Beach! |
I just read Ranciére's
Aesthetics and its Discontents, along with Adorno's essay "Extorted Reconciliation: On Georg Lukács'
Realism in Our Time" in an effort to parse out the complicated strands of politics, aesthetics, and the general critique of Modernism. Lukács famously and obtusely criticized Musil's Ulrich for his "worldlessness," as a bad example of the "decadent" tendencies of Modernist art; and Adorno defended both Musil and Modernist art from Lukács' charge on the grounds that Lukács was attempting an "extorted reconciliation" between reality and ideal which Modernist art emphatically resists. This resistance, inherent in Adorno's "negative dialectics," amounts to a form of political art which maintains its autonomy from affiliation and party program. Ranciére, compared to Adorno, is less critical of the realm of didactically political art (which he calls in one chapter "critical art" and which he divides up into the critical art of the earlier, supposedly more effective period of the 1920's to the 1970's roughly, and the current state of rather despair-driven works which Ranciére seems to see as more part of the problem than part of the solution, to borrow a phrase from the 60's). Yet he does mount a sort of defense of aesthetics and the Modernist program in Adorno's wake, arguing that the real issue is not about comparing postmodernism to modernism but, rather, realizing that Modernism itself has always been conscious of the necessary contradictions within it. Ranciére writes:
“Modernism itself has
only ever been a long contradiction between two opposed aesthetic politics, two
politics that are opposed but on the basis of a common core linking the
autonomy of art to the anticipation of a community to come, and therefore
linking this autonomy to the promise of its own suppression” (128).
I just read in Allen Tiher's Understanding Robert Musil that Musil, of course (of course?), rejected any idea of salvation (aesthetic redemption included?), including, presumably, the "anticipation of a community to come" that would entail, according to Ranciére, the demise of art's autonomy (because, presumably, alienation would be at an end, the millennium would arrive and everyone would be too happy making love to need to make art at all?!). Tiher, who doesn't mention anything about aesthetic redemption, the millennium, or the sort of complex intrinsically-destructing motion suggested by Ranciére at all (lest my association of the two suggest that he does), writes:
"It can be argued that Musil's failure to find a conclusion to his novel demonstrates the difficulty characterizing the modernist project of transforming or, indeed, saving culture through literary discourse. On making this observation, however, we should recall that he mocks the idea of salvation and saving culture as much as any other idea circulating in Vienna before the First World War---if this is not an idea taken from Weimar and projected back on Vienna...At some point during the writing of the novel saving culture became a cliché. ..From this perspective, if the novel's lack of completion illustrates a failure, it is the failure to create a discourse of salvation, a very modernist failure to create a viable myth" (230).
While it may be true that Musil mocks the idea of saving culture within the novel, it is important that we note Ulrich's proviso, referring, I believe, to the idea of the millennium or some other equally wild dream: “I only make fun of it because I love it" (II,817). Also, we must temper any of Musil's satirical comments on the possibility of creating a literary discourse of salvation in the novel with reference to his essays and addresses, particularly his notes for addresses during the reign of totalitarianism, where we see him engaged in a rather earnest "defense of culture" with the weapons of art. Which is not to imply that he meant that political battles could be fought by or with art. On the contrary, he maintained explicitly that the defense of culture meant that one could not fight political battles with pens and brushes; the best one could do was maintain the free non-affiliated voice of the artist as the last bastion of critical and non-conscripted thought, and encourage those whose job it was to use other kinds of weapons to understand that a large part of their job entailed protecting the autonomy of culture. Tiher's analysis suggests that the defense of culture was to be somehow better and more successfully waged with some other weapons than the tools the Modernists had at hand (maybe more up-to-date postmodernist weapons like the death of the author or the utter lack of differentiation between simulacrum and sense, or by a return to Social Realism perhaps?) and that the "failure" of Musil's novel is indicative of the generally agreed-upon consensus about the failure of Modernism to successfully negotiate the problems of engagement, politics, society, collectivism, culture. I do not mean to suggest that Tiher is advocating for a politicized art or even criticizing Musil and his project for their affiliation with discredited Modernism. Tiher is doing no such thing and his discussion of Musil is actually very nuanced and enlightening. It is just that it reveals that even in cases when a critic is not explicitly setting out to argue against Modernism or its aesthetic aims, there seems to be a somewhat unexamined assumption about the failure and misguidedness of the project, as if that were a given.
While the critique of aesthetic Modernism assumes already that a response and a resolution of political problems is, necessarily, the role of art, one might ask (as Musil did, albeit coming to no absolute conclusion) if such a task need be taken on by art at all. That being said, Tiher's analysis of the "failure" of Musil's novel to conclude as evidence of the failure of Modernism to come to a satisfactory conclusion, neglects a different reading of this lack of conclusion, one which I am sure Adorno would agree sees the lack of closure as much more active or proactive than passive. While Musil once wrote "Down with cultural optimism!" in a note about the attempts of his contemporaries to celebrate the coming salvation of the new Soviet era, he was not quite as pessimistic about the role and requirement of the artist to speak to, about, above, beyond the problems at hand; but this discussion was to be carried out with the tools of art, not those of demagoguery or party politics or didacticism or "extorted reconciliation". And he used the tools of art to resist the call to closure, to partisanship, to Gleichschaltung, by continuing to write, by refusing to come to final solution, by providing endless perspectives. Ranciére, looking out from the center at the two political positions he sees as inherent even in the so-called un-political aims of Modernism, writes:
“On the one hand, the
avant-garde movement aimed to transform the forms of art, and to make them
identical with the forms for constructing a new world in which art would no
longer exist as a separate reality. On the other, the avant-garde preserved the
autonomy of the artistic sphere from forms of compromise with practices of
power and political struggle, or with forms of aestheticization of life in the
capitalist world. ..This was not at all to preserve it for the pure enjoyment
of art for its own sake but, on the contrary , as the inscription of the unresolved
contradictions between the aesthetic promise and the realities of oppression in
the world” (129).
The phrase "unresolved contradictions" is reminiscent of both Musil and Adorno, and should remind us that aesthetics does not necessarily mean wholeness, completeness, or harmony, but can just as easily be an awareness of discord, dissonance, what Ranciére calls "dissensus" in contradiction to our beloved contemporary "consensus". As Adorno writes:
"The postulate of a reality that must be represented without a breach between subject and object and which must be 'reflected'---the term Lukács stubbornly adheres to---for the sake of that lack of a breach: that postulate, which is the supreme criterion of his aesthetics, implies that that reconciliation has been achieved, that society has been set right, that the subject has come into its own in its world. ...But the division, the antagonism, continues, and to say that it has been overcome in the nations of the Eastern Bloc, as they call it, is simply a lie [Adorno's essay was written in the 1960s]. The spell that holds Lukács in its power and bars his longed-for return to the utopia of his youth reenacts the extorted reconciliation he himself detected in absolute idealism" (240 Notes to Literature, Volume I).
While few people still believe today in the promises of the Soviet utopia, there are other utopias of reconciliation in the air, and the attempt to make the ever-shifting nature of truth fit in to a narrowly defined concept of good and right is probably always an anti-aesthetic attitude. It comes back to Carson's imperative to "keep the difference visible," or to Nietzsche's warning that we should not forget that the metaphoric unions that we make into meanings and truths are fictions and should be continually refreshed and reevaluated, since no two things are ever really the same, and never can really be fully reconciled. The “extorted
reconciliation,” in contrast, is the forced happy ending of the isolated subject’s reunion with
world and society, progress, success.
But why the need to
justify art at all, this defensive stance. From where this need to argue that aesthetics has
political and social value, that aesthetics is ethics, that there is a link
between aesthetics and conduct of life? Of course in so far the way we see the
world determines our ethics, aesthetics is inherently connected to ethics, and Musil certainly saw it that way. If
aesthetics made us callow craven indifferent cruel sadists (Zizek suggests as much in an essay comparing de Sade and
Kant!), if it made us Dorian Grays with hidden atrocities in our closets, if
aesthetics were merely a way to cover up ugly truths, then perhaps the attack
would be justified. But if aesthetics is, as I believe, a conscious attention, concern
and value applied to surfaces, shapes, arrangements, techniques, dynamics,
movement, suspensions, densities, repetition and their expressive powers, as
opposed to a limited focus only on ideas, ideologies, content, message, political program, action,
expediency, utility, practicality, materialism, then a defense of aesthetics
amounts to a defense of the imagination, of pleasure, of human sensual and
intellectual freedom, curiosity, play (defined by Kant and Schiller), essay, experimentation, openness.
While the anti-aesthetic privileging of content over form
seems on the surface to be a favoring of the transcendental Platonic Idea over vulgar materialism
of the flesh, in fact it amounts to just the opposite, since the formal games
of art are respites from the materiality of the world of profit, loss, purpose,
use, they are (as Lukács complains) “worldless” in the sense that they (contrary
to his intent) imagine new and other worlds, in that they cannot be
commodified, in that they are of no earthly use, and thus confound the philistine, the
ideologue, the agitator and the capitalist merchant, who do not know how to
sell what is most valuable about them. That they are free. Wilde wrote that the "cynic is a man who knows the price of everything and the value of nothing". This is, in fact, a critique of materialism by one of the most extreme aesthetes of literary history, a proponent of the truth of masks and the depths of surfaces. The shape of a poem,
its cadences, surprises, sounds, spaces, cannot be commodified, and cannot be
taken as booty by either side, cannot be turned into slogan or party program.
Musil's defense of culture amounted to a defense of Geist as realm of aesthetic play, critical
non-affiliation, subjunctive and, yes, subjective perspectivism (why should the
individual’s perspective be suspect?). When infinite and defracted perspective is simplified down to the common
denominator (the lowest common denominator, by the way), it is by definition
less complex, less comprehensive, less, to use a word with some value for some
people who attack aesthetics for its supposed escapism, less “real”. Reality is not some ideal of
good or right or moral, but, rather, a constantly changing, shifting complexity
of values, desires, choices, imaginings and perspectives. Something we make together, out of our differences. Which is not to say
that nothing matters or that there is no way to approach truth or attempt right
action, but, rather, that to do so is far more interesting and complex and challenging than communally
establishing (from above, by the way, despite claims of populism) what is right or wrong or correct or
incorrect and then attempting, rigidly, to make artists and other creative
individuals adhere to that system.
The activity of the
free realm of aesthetics turns out, despite itself, to be political, social, ethical; and this not by
virtue of its supposed attempt to conceal the reality of suffering or to
maintain the entrenched values of the people in power, but because it is
intrinsically a realm which cannot breathe when constricted by dogma, coercion,
or “extorted reconciliation”. The aesthetic is not
only anathema to oppression, not only political thus in negativity or
non-collaboration with programs or systems, but also positively, affirmatively,
in its natural generation of new ideas, forms, desires, possibilities, its
active proliferation of human energies…and, gasp, its love of existing in the world. As Nietzsche would remind us: Amor fati. Love of fate! In all its unreconciled beauty and horror!